Variations on a beauty theme: The uses of ‘normal’
In this post, our Principal Investigator, Heather Widdows, considers the concept of normality in the context of the beauty debate.
The current beauty ideal is becoming more dominant and
narrower and it is harder to resist and reject. This makes it difficult to
regard the ‘choices’ we make with regard to beauty as ‘free choice’ (See here).
I’ve demonstrated this using the example of the increasing demands of body
hair removal. Taken together I argue that the beauty ideal demands more; it
applies to more types of women, for longer and is global (see my last post). In
this post I want to focus on the various ways in which ‘normal’ functions in
the beauty debate.
The concept of ‘normal’ and how it is interpreted, perceived
and used in the beauty debate has emerged as a key ethical concern in all of
the Beauty Demands workshops (and from across academic disciplines). Some of
these ways are overtly normative, and others are apparently neutral but carry
hidden normative assumptions, and others are used as if they are descriptive.
Let us just consider a few ways in which ‘normal’ can be used in the beauty
context.
First, ‘normal’ is used in discussions of motivation for
cosmetic surgery and other body modification practices. ‘To be normal’ is used
as a motivating reason to justify engaging in beauty practices or procedures.
‘To be normal’ as a motivating reason is often contrasted to other motivating
reasons (like ‘to be perfect’ or ‘to be beautiful’). ‘To be normal’ seems to be
regarded as a ‘good’ reason. For instance, ‘to be normal’, doesn’t carry connotations
of improvement or enhancement or even vanity which might be thought to connect
to less acceptable reasons.
Second, ‘normal’ is used in at least some medical discourse
to distinguish between ‘justified’ surgery and other surgery. Sometimes this
will be connected to the funding of surgery. For example, in some contexts some
surgery will be funded by insurance companies or others if it is regarded as
‘treatment’ and in some contexts this parallels with ‘attaining the norm’. At
other times it will be used to signal that the client/patient does not have
unreasonable expectations of surgery. For obvious reasons practitioners are
concerned if someone seeking an intervention has unrealistic expectations of
the transformative power of surgery. Accordingly ‘to be normal’ has become the
acceptable language for attaining surgery.
Given that ‘normal’ is now an acceptable motivating and
justifying reason to engage in all sorts of beauty procedures – including, but by no means limited to,
surgery – it is not surprising that it is functioning in a wholly normative way
as a value-judgement to signify what is desirable. For example, those who seek
breast enhancement or reduction and use the language of ‘to be normal’ (bigger,
smaller, perter, firmer). But breasts of all kinds of shapes and sizes are
‘normal’ in the sense that they are functional as sexual and reproductive
organs. Therefore ‘normal’ must mean something different. The woman seeking
augmentation or reduction is suggesting that her breasts don’t look normal to
her. But – and this is a key point – notions of ‘normal’ here are difficult to
consider ‘objective’. What is a normal sized breast? Is it some average
measurement? Should breasts which fall at the extreme end of scale of inches
and cup-size be deemed ‘abnormal’? Or is it more subjective, about what the
women (and practitioner) consider a normal shape and size? If it is the later
then how do we come up with our concept of ‘normal’? Is the ‘normal breast’ the
one’s we’d ideally like (which would be a strange use of ‘normal’)? Or is the
‘normal breast’ the one we normally see (presumably in the media)? If so then
our notion of ‘normal’ is often, perhaps standardly, of a breast with an
implant (as while breast implants are being ‘normalised’ there are still a
higher proportion of those in the media who have implants when compared to
those not in the public eye). This consideration of ‘normal’ raises a number of
issues:
First, the use of ‘normal’ as motivating and justificatory
reasons are presented as if it is descriptive, but in fact here ‘normal’ is
functioning to ethically signal (and perhaps even demarcate) reasonable and
acceptable surgery. This use of ‘normal’ needs to be interrogated. If the
procedure (and perhaps the outcome) is the same should it matter what
motivations are? If so why? Perhaps one could justify this (as practitioners
do) because those with aspirations to be ‘normal’ present with clear ideas
about what needs to be ‘fixed’, rather than expecting an unrealistic
transformation, and are less likely to be disappointed. But, this would need
further justification. Further, the language of normal can be learned – if this
is the acceptable discourse then we will all use it to access the procedures we
desire.
Second, if ‘normal’ becomes that which is acceptable what
happens to those who fall significantly outside the ‘normal range’? What of
those with bodies and body parts which are ‘abnormal’: and not just a little
outside the range, but dramatically so and without possibility that a technical
fix could make them ‘normal’. To use ‘normal’ as an ethical demarcator raises
issues of discrimination for those who fall outside the norm (and here we
should take note of the criticisms made by disability rights advocates). Is it
really the case that ‘normal’ is something we should value?
Third, as more of those who can use technical fixes to
become ‘normal’ do so, then what is normal will become narrower and harder to
attain. Some who are ‘normal’ now may not be ‘normal’ in the future: as more
become ‘normal’ what was once normal will become the outlier and, eventually,
‘abnormal’. Moreover, it might become regarded as unethical not to use a
process or procedure to attain ‘normal’ (irrespective of health or other
goods). This is both a function of the technological imperative – as
technological possibilities become more available then there is more pressure
to use them – and of the increasing homogenisation of beauty norms – as there
is increased pressure to conform to the ever higher demands of the beauty
ideal.
Perhaps ‘normal’ isn’t so ‘normal’ after all…
Professor Widdows’ research is funded by the Leverhulme
Trust and she holds a Major Research Fellowship (details
here). Her book, Perfect Me!, is under contract with Princeton University
Press.
Thank you for this post, Heather, it is very interesting. All the questions that you ask are very pertinent and I think that they truly need to be addressed if we want to use the term ‘normal’ when it comes to beauty procedures.
ReplyDeleteLet’s take the medical context. You mention how the notion is sometimes used to mark justified surgery, how it can make the difference between treatment (which entails that it is, in some way, necessary) and a simple desire, and also how it can impact on the distribution of funding. These are not small issues and that is why I think further qualifications need to be made here: if we talk about treatment and necessity, then we need to talk about what theory of health and disease is being used.
When one wants to say that one needs the cosmetic surgery as a treatment, in order to be normal, we need to know more about this normal. If it is the kind of normal that the original functionalist theory of health and disease, most famously formulated by Christian Boorse, then a lot of cosmetic procedures would not enter the category (for example, as you mention, breast size has rarely, if ever, anything to do with its functionality). Additionally — and ironically — because of his desire to keep the term ‘normal’ as value-free, Boorse claimed that something being abnormal does not entail that it needs to be treated and fixed (Boorse, 1977); the term itself, along with other such as health and disease, don’t say anything about what should be done. Also, to go along these lines to argue for cosmetic surgery would be very difficult, as the functionalist account focuses a lot on the relation of normality with things such as function, reference class and efficiency, which would be extremely hard to pin down in this context.
So, if it’s not the functionalist view, is it the normativist account then? Even though the people who hold this view do not usually talk about normality, they do talk about disease as something being bad for us and our goals, something we have an aversion towards and we do not want (this is, of course, very roughly put, as there are many versions of normativism, some weaker, some stronger). Then many — too many probably! — of what we consider imperfections, which impede us from achieving different goals, should be seen as diseases and should be funded as legitimate treatments.
It seems, then, that what is ‘normal’ is very difficult to define in medicine when it comes to cosmetic surgery. And, overall, given that each of us brings with herself/himself their own idea of ‘normal’, concerning beauty procedures, the concept can do little work or, even worse, it may actually do damage. Therefore, I think it is rather dangerous to transfer the term ‘normal’ in the beauty discourse, especially in the context of the homogenisation of beauty standards (a process which is ethically suspicious in itself), and perhaps we should refrain ourselves from doing so.